Financial Markets
Department of Mathematical Sciences, Aalborg University
This course serves as an “introduction” to financial theory.
Both mathematical and economic aspects are discussed.
Among others, the following topics will be covered:
* choices under certainty
* expected utility and risk taking
* mean-variance diagram
* minimum variance portfolio
* Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM) and evidence
* Arbitrage Pricing Theory (APT) and evidence
Evaluation is pass/fail.
It is a “running evaluation”, so working through the semester is required to pass.
We will use GitHub for handling the (5) self-study sessions.
You have to “commit” your solutions as proof of participation.
Finance is the science of managing resources and investments, including the creation and analysis of derivative products.
At is core, finance deals with the notion of uncertainty: returns on investments are unknown a-priori.
So the question arises on how/why trading is done.
Which brings us to talk about how to model decisions under different choices.
We start by abstracting from randomness.
To model consumers’ choices, we define a set of choices \(X\subset \mathbb{R}^n\), and a weak preference relation \(\succsim\).
\(X\) is typically composed of \(n\) “goods”.
For \(x,y\in X\), we say that \(x\) is at least as preferred as \(y\) if \(x\succsim y\).
The pair \((X,\succsim)\) characterizes the agent’s choice problem.
From the weak preference relation we can define:
Moreover, the indifference curve for \(x\) by \(\{y\in X: x\sim y\}\).
Analogously, the lower and upper contour sets.
The fact that we consider the components of \(X\) to be “goods” can be used to show that the preference relation is strongly monotone.
Strong monotonicity
The preference relation \(\succsim\) on \(X\) is strongly monotone if for \(x,y\in X\) with \(y\geq x\) and \(y\neq x\), then \(y\succ x\).
Strong monotonicity is colloquially stated as “more is better”.
We assume that the preference relation satisfies the rationality assumption.
Rationality assumption
The preference relation \(\succsim\) on the set of choices \(X\) is said to be rational if it satisfies:
Completeness: \(\forall x,y\in X\), it holds that \(x\succsim y\) or \(y\succsim x\).
Transitivity: \(\forall x,y,z\in X\), if \(x\succsim y\) and \(y\succsim z\), then \(x\succsim z\)
Failings of rationality:
Utility functions are defined so that we can use our mathematical tools for the analysis.
Definition
We say that \(u:X\rightarrow\mathbb{R}\) is a utility function representing the preference relation \(\succsim\) if \[x\succsim y \ \ \Leftrightarrow \ \ u(x)\geq u(y), \ \ \ \ \forall x,y\in X.\]
In short, utility functions take us from the “abstract” space of bundles and preferences to the real line.
The existence of an utility function is not guaranteed unless the preference relation satisfies the continuity assumption.
Continuity assumption
The preference relation \(\succsim\) on the set of choices \(X\) is said to be continuous if \(\forall x\in X\), the sets \(\{y\in X:y\succsim x\}\) and \(\{y\in X:x\succsim y\}\) are closed.
That is the lower and upper contour sets are closed.
In fact, for continuous preference relations (plus extra conditions), we can show that there exists a continuous utility function that represents them.
Theorem (Existence of utility function)
Let \(\succsim\) be a strongly monotone, rational, and continuous preference relation on \(X\). Then, there is a continuous utility function \(u(\cdot)\) that represents \(\succsim\).
Proof for the existence of utility function theorem.
Note that the utility function from the Theorem is only guaranteed to be continuous.
Nonetheless, in practice we usually require it to be (twice) differentiable for the analysis.
Additional conditions as homotheticity, (quasi)-linearity, and quasiconcavity are sometimes required.
Cobb-Douglas utility function: \(u(x,y) = K x^\alpha y^{1-\alpha}\)
Cobb-Douglas utility function: \(u(x,y) = K x^\alpha y^{1-\alpha}\)
Monotonic transformations of utility functions represent the same preference relation.
Utility functions are downward sloping.
Each indifference curve is a level set of the utility function.
Each bundle is part of an indifference curve.
Two indifference curves cannot intersect.
With the utility function defined, the two extra components required to solve the agent’s choice problem are:
Under these conditions, the (Walrasian) budget set is given by \[B_{p,w} := \{x\in X: p\cdot x\leq w\}.\]
The choice problem of a rational agent with utility function \(u(\cdot)\), wealth \(w\), and prices \(p\) is given by:
\[\max u(x) \text{ s.t. } p\cdot x \leq w.\]
Theorem (Solution of Agent’s choice problem)
If \(p>0\) and \(u(\cdot)\) is continuous, then the utility maximization problem has a solution.
Department of Mathematical Sciences